84. Thomas Aquinas is often
described as Aristotelian. How do
Aquinas’ views in moral philosophy exemplify or challenge Aristotelian
assumptions about the moral life?
Give two specific examples of how Aquinas both appropriates and corrects
Aristotle on the moral life.
I)
Intro
A) Setup
1) Aristotle’s influence on Thomas
B) Thesis
1) While the Aristotelian
notions of eudaimonia and virtue are central to Aquinas’ ethical thought,
Aquinas has a very different view of the highest good and of the virtues that
help one reach that highest good.
C) Map
1) Aristotle on Eudaimonia and Virtue
2) Aquinas on Eudaimonia
3) Aquinas on Virtue
II)
Aristotle on Eudaimonia and Virtue
A) Eudaimonia
1) The nature of eudaimonia
(a) The ultimate/highest end of
human life is “eudaimonia” or happiness.
(b) Happiness is an activity–specifically,
it is the activity that uses the highest faculties of man excellently.
(c) Thus what is good for man is
determined by man’s function.
(d) Since man’s unique function (i.e.,
what sets him apart from other creatures) is to apprehend a rational principle,
the human good is an activity of the soul implying a rational principle carried
out excellently.
(e) That is, happiness is
activity of the soul in accordance with virtue.
2) Further Aristotelian theses
(a) Eudaimonia is ultimately
found in the life of contemplation, primarily contemplation of the unmoved
mover
(b) Eudaimonia can be achieved
in this life
(c) Eudaimonia can be achieved
through natural human powers
B) Virtue
1) The nature of virtue
(a) Virtue is an enduring
disposition concerned with a choice, lying in a mean, determined by a rational
principle as the man of practical wisdom would determine it.
(b) There are both intellectual
and moral virtues
2) Further Aristotelian theses
(a) The intellectual virtues are
the highest, as they are most intimately tied to humanity’s highest
faculty/function.
(b) Given Aristotle’s view of
the highest good as natural, the virtues are all naturally achievable through
habituation and/or learning.
III) Aquinas on
Eudaimonia
A) Aquinas’ appropriation: Acceptance of the framework
1) Like Aristotle, Thomas argues
that there must be an ultimate end, which he identifies with human
happiness/wellbeing. (So his view also is eudaimonistic.)
2) Like Aristotle, Thomas
describes happiness as an activity of our highest faculty directed toward its
highest object.
B) Aquinas’ correction: Radically different content
1) The object of contemplation
(a) For Aquinas the highest
human good, perfect happiness, is the comprehension of God (through our
speculative intellect) in the beatific vision.
(b) Aristotle’s view that the
greatest happiness is found in this-worldly contemplation of the first mover is
very different.
2) Perfect happiness cannot be
had in this life, but can be attained in the afterlife
(a) Happiness in this life is
incomplete
(i) Aquinas does not reject
Aristotle’s conception of happiness, but argues that it is (by Aristotle’s own
standard) a description of the imperfect happiness attainable in this life.
(ii) This imperfection extends
even to the life of contemplation, since it lacks security. (Intellectual virtues deal with things that
are good by participation rather than goodness itself, i.e. God.)
(b) The conditions of this life
are not conducive to perfect happiness
(i) Hardship, ignorance,
inevitable death and loss
(c) The nature of the
appreciation required for perfect happiness is not possible in this life
(i) The mode of knowledge
depends on the nature of the knower.
(ii) While we live in this life
we have a form in corporeal matter, so we can only know other things that have
such a form, or things which can be inferred from them. [1,12,11].
(d) Thus, perfect happiness,
which is found in the beatific vision, is to be found only in the afterlife.
3) Grace
(a) Ultimately, happiness cannot be attained by natural
human power, but must be granted by God through grace.
IV) Aquinas on
Virtue
A) Aquinas’ appropriation: Acceptance of the framework
1) Aquinas’ concept of virtue
is very close to Aristotle’s
(a) A virtue is a habit that
perfects a power or faculty with respect to an act.
(b) Virtues make something work
well; every human virtue is ordered toward the proper use of free choice.
(c) Also, like Aristotle, he
says that virtues are means as regards their essence but extremes in terms of
excellence.
2) Thomas agrees with Aristotle
on the character of many of the virtues
(a) Cardinal virtues: Aristotle
does not designate cardinal virtues, but as Aquinas describes them they aren’t
antithetical to anything in Aristotle
(b) The cardinal virtues can be
thought of as the principle virtues associated with various faculties of the
soul:
(i) The power that is rational
in essence (i.e. intellect) – prudence
(ii) Three powers that are
rational by participation
(i) Will – justice
(ii) Concupiscible appetite –
temperance
(iii) Irascible appetite –
fortitude
B) Aquinas’ correction: Supernatural content
1) Human happiness is twofold.
(a) To achieve imperfect
happiness our natural powers (though not without divine aid) are sufficient.
(b) But to achieve our ultimate
end, our natural powers—and therefore the perfection of those powers in natural
virtues, both moral and intellectual—will be ultimately insufficient
(i) This can be seen from the
fact that they aim at an end we understand, while God is beyond our
understanding.
(ii) We need principles (sources
of action) surpassing human nature.
(iii) God gives us these in the
form of the theological virtues, a
special participation in the divine nature granted by grace.
2) The theological virtues
(a) Why the theological virtues
are so named
(i) Their object is God
(ii) They must be given by God
(since they are beyond human nature)
(iii) They are made known only by
divine revelation (which may suggest a reason why Aristotle, working from human
reason, wasn’t aware of them).
(b) The function of the theological virtues
(i) They give us an accurate
conception of our ultimate end (faith), the desire to attain it even though it
is arduous (hope), and the beginning of supernatural rectitude of will
(charity). More specifically, the functions of the virtues are:
(ii) Faith
aids the intellect in grasping
supernatural principles via divine light
(iii) Hope
directs will to our ultimate end as
something possible to attain
(iv) Charity brings about spiritual union by conforming the will to that end. It is the measure of our participation in the
inner life of God (and the determinant of the degree to which we can experience
the beatific vision).
(c) This is a major departure
from Aristotle
(i) All the virtues Aristotle discussed
could be attained through learning or habituation.
(ii) For Aristotle, the
intellectual virtues are the highest; for Aquinas, the theological virtues are
the highest
FYI: Material available on
A. Freddoso’s website was very useful in understanding Aquinas on some of these
points. Specifically, under “courses”, Freddoso lists a class on Aquinas’
ethics, and in the course materials you can find excellent notes on the
“Treatise on Happiness” and “Treatise on Virtue”. (www.nd.edu/~afreddos/)
No comments:
Post a Comment