51. Explain and evaluate
Aristotle’s proposed explanation of akrasia
(weakness of will) in Nicomachean Ethics
7.
RW:
There was only one previous outline, which I used but added to (mostly based on
Roberts notes) and rearranged.
I)
Intro
A) Set-up
1) The context in NE
B) Overview
1) Aristotle is
concerned both with giving an account of akrasia (and neighboring notions), as
well as solving the apparent paradox of knowing the good but failing to do
it. Akrasia (=incontinence) is
when someone partakes of bodily pleasure in excess because their appetites keep
them from standing by their deliberation not to act in that way. (Note: their
reason for so acting is NOT that they think it best to engage excessively in
bodily pleasures.) This occurs
through a sort of ignorance (namely, ignorance of the minor premise in a
practical syllogism). Incontinence
is incompatible with prudence.
C) Map
1) What is akrasia?
(Disambiguate its species, and compare/contrast related concepts)
2) Incontinence and knowledge
3) Incontinence and prudence
4) Evaluation
II)
What is akrasia?
A) Akrasia = Incontinence
1) The incontinent are distinguished from others by their
concerns (i.e., desires, appetites)
and their attitudes toward their
concerns (i.e., they recognize they are not right to pursue)
(a) Lacks control/mastery over himself, specifically over
his nonrational appetites
(b) Has the correct decision, but acts on appetite instead
(i.e., he thinks act X is wrong to pursue, yet still pursues it)
(c) Roberts’ example:
(i) Incontinence
is exemplified when somebody who knows a course of action to be the best
knowingly takes a bad or less good course of action instead, out of attraction
to the latter. Consider the person who knows that his eudaimonia depends on
his having a “happy” marriage and that this in turn depends on his being
faithful to his wife. But he is tempted to have an affair with a very beautiful
and interesting woman at work who repeatedly coaxes him and makes him offers.
Let us say that this man is a thinking person and has a clear understanding of
what makes for his eudaimonia, and he understands why having this affair will
ruin it. This man would exemplify incontinence if, due to the attractions of
the woman, the excitement, and the pleasure of having the affair, he forsook
his eudaimonia by having the affair.
2) = The person prone to be overcome by their appetite
for pleasures
(a) Cf. Continent
= the person who overcomes his appetites (e.g., the man who overcomes his
appetites and so does not have the affair described above)
(b) Cf. Soft =
the person who is overcome by pains.
(Whereas the incontinent turn from the right course because of attraction to pleasure, the soft turn
aside because of repulsion from pain. Roberts’ E.g.: the man who won’t climb
a ladder to save his child from a burning building because of fear of heights)
(c) Cf. Resistant
= the person who overcomes pains (e.g., the man who climbs the ladder, despite
his fear)
B) Species of Incontinence
1) Differences in the object of incontinence
(a) We call some
people incontinent in respect of ...
(anger, honor, etc.)
(i) This is not
really incontinence, but rather an excess which should be avoided. They are
called incontinent only analogically.
(b) Simple incontinence
(i) We call
people incontinent in the unqualified sense when they are concerned with bodily enjoyments (i.e., the same
subject matter as intemperance)
(ii) Note: We do
not call someone incontinent if they act so due to nature or because they are
in a morbid state.
2) Differences
in deliberation
(a) Weakness: the person deliberates, but his
feelings make him abandon the result of his deliberation
(b) Impetuosity: Led on by feelings because he has
not deliberated. E.g.,
quick-tempered and ardent people.
(c) Weakness is
worse than impetuosity.
C) Compare/contrast Intemperance
1) Concerned in a way with the same pleasures and pains, but
not in the same way
(a) The intemperate person pursues excesses of pleasure
because they are excesses and because he decides on them (i.e., he thinks they
are right); the intemperate person has no regrets, and so is incurable.
(b) The incontinent doesn’t so decide; they are curable
2) Intemperance is worse than incontinence
(a) It is worse to act shamefully from no/weak appetite
than from intense appetite
(b) The incontinent is more easily persuaded out of bad
acts
3) Incontinence is not, strictly speaking, a vice, though
it is one in a way.
(a) Incontinence conflicts with decision; vice expresses
decision
(b) Yet it is similar to vice in action.
D) The relative goodness/badness of the various states of
character
1) From best to worst: divine excellence, virtue,
continence, resistance, incontinence, softness, vice, bestial.
III) Incontinence
and Knowledge
A) Puzzle: Some (e.g., Socrates) thought one who knows
the good will do the good.
B) Solution: We can have knowledge in two ways
1) Dispositional knowledge: Have knowledge, without
attending to it
(a) Acting incontinently against such knowledge is not extraordinary
2) Episodic knowledge: Have knowledge, with attending to
it
(a) Acting incontinently against such knowledge is extraordinary
C) Need knowledge of general and particular premises (in
practical syllogism)
1) The incontinent may only know the general premise, but
not the particular premise (or, perhaps more accurately, he knows the
particular premise only dispositionally, though he may have known it episodically
if he weren’t impeded by passions, etc.) – e.g., they may know that act-type X
is bad, yet don’t realize that act A falls under that type, and so fail to act
in accord with the general premise
D) Use of knowledge can be impeded by our condition
1) Drunkenness, strong emotions, sexual appetites, etc.
2) Incontinent people “say the words in the way that
actors do” – they don’t appreciate what
they are saying.
E) Conclusion: Incontinence reduces to (at least
temporary) ignorance
1) The incontinent person acts against knowledge by, in one
of the ways just outlined, breaking the connection between their knowledge of
the good and their assessment of the situation before them.
2) But he doesn’t act against the highest form of
knowledge; just the knowledge of the particular premise
IV) Incontinence
and Prudence
A) The
incontinent person cannot be practically wise
1) Practical
wisdom consists of not only knowing but also acting; since the incontinent man is unable to act, he cannot be practically
wise.
2) The
incontinent man can be clever, though.
3) The
incontinent man is “like a city which passes all the right decrees and has good
laws, but makes no use of them”.
V)
Evaluation
of Aristotle’s explanation
A) Evaluate as you see fit!
B) My evaluation (influenced by Roberts notes)
1) Much of the conceptual analysis seems mostly right to
me (e.g., helpful disambiguations)
2) I don’t think acting against knowledge of the good is
always reducible to temporary ignorance.
(a) Big missing piece: deficit in the will itself, even with
knowledge of good.
(b) Deficit in the will can be rooted in a deficit of concern for the good, or a deficit of effort to stay on the right path.
3) It isn’t obvious to me that it is always easier to
cure incontinence than intemperance
(a) It seems that changing the will/appetites (which is
needed for curing incontinence) can be harder in some instances than retraining
moral judgments (which is needed for curing intemperance, and by which an
intemperate person can come to feel regret)
No comments:
Post a Comment